The concept of anticipation is not new; medical and other researchers wrote about anticipation in the course of the nineteenth century. The mental physiologist W. B. Carpenter introduced the concept ideo-motor action to desсribe the way self-willed or automatic thoughts took control over the bodily organs; the concept provided a basic framework for understanding the course and generation of illness [34, 13]. The term, the anticipating (sic!) imagination, was not uncommon in popular literature on science, and even in Christian theology. It was used, for instance, to explain psychic phenomena which could be observed at seances of table-turning. The unconscious was widely understood in terms of expectations and sub-conscious anticipation. Later, however, Hayward argues [34, 12], the interpretation of the unconscious processes changed: thus, Freud linked them to past events, especially to childhood memories, rather than to the anticipated future. The unconscious psyche was now understood as a collection of traumatic memories and frustrated desires rather than as a capacity for anticipating events. This interpretation Pavlov shared with Freud, in spite of all their disagreement. By contrast with Pavlov and many others, Bernstein was interested in the determination of the action by the future. His brief article in Science and Life, with which we opened this paper, confirmed this once again.
By quoting Bernstein’s productive formula “Posture is a preparation for action” [20, 88], the physiologist Alain Berthoz reminded us that Bernstein was one of the first to conceive anticipation as a constructive element of movement. In the early 2000s, Berthoz, who considers himself Bernstein’s student, and the philosopher Jean-Luc Petit wrote a book-length study The Physiology and Phenomenology of Action, quoted above. Amongst other questions, they touch on two linked concepts: anticipation and kinaesthetic imagination. They saw the roots of the concepts in Kant’s philosophy. Kant wrote that “motion <…> considered as the describing of a space, is a pure act of the successive synthesis of the manifold in outer intuition in general by means of the productive imagination and belongs not only to geometry, but even to transcendental philosophy” [20, 92–93]. Following Kant, the authors distinguished between schema — an image which implies vision, and schemata (scheme) — a powerful concept in psychology which implies action, movement and the body. Imagination is a faculty of schemata. The key idea underlying Kant’s schematism, as Berthoz and Petit understood it, is our constant schematisation of experience. Kant attributed this structure either to the faculty of imagination or to the faculty of understanding claiming that, to the extent that it proceeds from our spontaneity, it consists of a natural poetics [20, 117–119]. How, Berthoz and Petit asked, can these formal aspects be manifest in something, namely the subject, who is essentially temporal? They answered: the formal aspects are manifest through the actions of anticipation accomplished by the perceiving subject. In relation to this, Berthoz referred to his memories from 1970 when he was a guest of the Russian physiologist A.S. Batuev at the Pavlov Institute in Leningrad. He remembered his joy on seeing the neuronal activity of the auditory system of an animal in Batuev’s laboratory. These neurones responded vigorously to the natural meowing of a cat but were completely indifferent to any pure sound in the same wave frequency. The brain, Berthoz commented, is definitely interested in meaningful events in the physical world belonging to its Umwelt. “The decisive step in neurophysiology”, he claims, “is therefore a transition from a bottom-up neurophysiology to a top-down neurophysiology, a physiology of anticipation” [20, 129–130].
It might be suggested that Berthoz and Petit inherited this stand from the phenomenologist, Maurice Merleau-Ponty. The latter argued that, in order for spectators to activate their kinaesthetic imagination, they need to experience participation in the performer’s movement rhythms. Merleau-Ponty discussed kinaesthesia in terms of “intentionality” or “goal-directedness”. He argued that an attitude of openness towards a future movement was inseparable from a corporeal experience in the present, which he described as being neither a movement nor a mental representation of a movement, but rather “an anticipation of, or arrival at, the objective <…> ensured by the body itself as a motor power, a ‘motor project’ <…> a ‘motor intentionality’” [35, 187]. The French kinaesiologist and dance scholar, Hubert Godard, continues the tradition. He argues that “virtual” (anticipated or imagined) movement is itself a physical event. Godard describes as “pre-movement” the process whereby a set of muscles contracts in anticipation of a movement to be performed by a different part of the body. For instance, if we ask a person in the upright position to raise her arm, the first muscles to contract will be those of the ankle and leg: thus the body anticipates the need for balancing the changed center of gravity that will result from lifting the arm. Modern neuroscience contends that such a pre-movement starts about a quarter of a second before the main action (here, the raising of the arm) begins, indicating that pre-movement is not a localised reflex action but rather, originates in the brain triggered by the formation of the intention to move [35, 13].
The philosopher Susan A. J. Stuart writes on the role of anticipation and connected notions of apperception and kinaesthetic imagination [36; 37]. She and others use the wonderful word plenisentient to describe the way the body is switched on to the world, perceiving, receiving, imagining, anticipating, and actuating. The plenisentient experience of movement assures the deep pre-cognitive kinaesthetic relationships with the world which makes its conceptualisation possible.
The term kinaesthetic imagination was perhaps introduced in the first decades of the twentieth century. The American dance scholar John Martin argued that we all are equipped with a sixth sense of kinaesthesis – the capacity to act gracefully and to apprehend directly the actions or the dynamic abilities of other people or objects [32, 228]. Even earlier, William James in his famous Principles of Psychology (in the chapter on imagination) discussed the issue of motor imagery: whether it was a “resuscitated feeling” arising in the body parts that had been influenced by prior movements. It was not until the 1980s that the true motor nature of motor imagery was fully recognised. This move was a noted contribution of sport psychologists [38, v].
As the phenomenologist Maxine Sheets-Johnstone shows, we need kinaesthetic imagination both for performing our own movements and perceiving the motion of other persons and objects. For instance, in the case of a dancer moving along a circular line, “we form an imaginative Gestalt of the movement by apprehending each moment of the circle as a spatial-temporal present in relation to a spatial-temporal past and future: the present is a flight out of the past towards a future. It is a transitory moment of an imaginative spatial-temporal whole and not an isolated present. Consequently, there is not a succession of images but a single and unbroken circular line” [39, 116]. This is undoubtedly a product of kinaesthetic imagination.
For a number of years, Dee Reynolds, with collaborators, has been working on a project “Watching Dance”, to investigate kinaesthetic empathy — an ability to perceive and understand movements (including dance) of other people. She also uses the term kinesthetic imagination for the bringing about of “movement events that disrupt normative, habitual ways of using energy in movement and produce innovations in production, distribution, expenditure and retention of energy in the body”. These acts, she claims, involve a delicate balance between determinism and agency. The function of kinaesthetic imagination can be viewed as an activity that works with sign systems to destabilize fixed meaning and representations [35, 4].
Kinaesthetic imagination can have multiple practical outcomes. Virtual or imagined movement can be used to learn new skills, as happens when athletes repeatedly visualise correctly executed movements when learning to perform difficult manoeuvres. Mental rehearsal is now included in rehabilitation procedures for patients suffering from pathological motor impairments and associated troubles, like phantom pain and post-stroke and post-traumatic movement disorders. Some recent studies suggest that activation of the motor system during motor imagery is not identical to that during motor execution (the distribution of activity in the two modalities only partially overlaps, and the activity within the motor cortex is weaker during imagery than during execution) [38, vi]. Yet, kinaesthetic imagination has found its way into clinical practice and research.